In our era, the idea is widespread that the world can be an orderly whole, in which states adhere to clear and indispensable rules and principles that apply equally to all. In other words, it is believed that a legal order similar to that which exists within a state can be established in international relations and in conflicts between states, and that there can be a judicial path to determine who is right and who is wrong, punishing those who break the rules (through international tribunals).
Within a state, there is a
recognized authority that enacts
precise laws and to which
citizens are subject: so is it
truly possible to establish such
an order at the international
level, where these prerequisites
do not exist?
Let’s try to answer this
question.
Let’s examine one of the fundamental principles: no state may attack another state. Consider a commonly discussed case around the world (in the West, at least): in the conflict in Ukraine, Russia is the aggressor, Ukraine is the victim, and therefore, in order to preserve not only Ukraine but the global order, one must fight alongside Ukraine against Russia—it seems self-evident.
But in fact, it is not so self-evident, especially if not only Russia but also the majority of the world (China, India, and many other countries) do not at all share this interpretation of the facts.
Let’s try applying this principle to other historical events. By such a standard, Italy’s wars of independence would have been acts of aggression against Austria—just like the Expedition of the Thousand, ambiguously supported by Cavour. Yet we Italians glorify those events, view them as just, and speak of the Risorgimento, because they aligned with the principle of the nation-state: every nation has the right to its own state, that is, to freedom. Of course, this principle was not universally accepted—indeed, most Italians at the time did not support it, and it was mainly popular among the educated bourgeoisie.
Now consider the outbreak of World War II. Germany’s invasions of Czechoslovakia and then Poland were also justified by the principle of nationality, as Germany aimed to annex (liberate) lands mostly populated by Germans (the Sudetenland, Danzig, and the German Baltic). Formally, it was France and the UK that declared war on Germany. In this case, however, we believe that annexing (liberating) those German-speaking lands was merely a pretext for expansion, subjugation of other peoples, and seizure of what was called Lebensraum, with the ultimate goal of German domination over all of Europe. This interpretation seems well-founded: Germany was entirely in the wrong, the Allies entirely in the right.
Thus, a political criterion was adopted, opposite to that of our Risorgimento.
If we consider later events, we
find similar political
processes.
The USSR intervened in Poland,
Hungary, and Czechoslovakia
claiming to defend the communist
revolution against capitalist
plots. The U.S. intervened in
Korea, Vietnam, Cuba, and many
other places claiming to fight
for freedom against the
communist threat. After 9/11,
the invasions of Afghanistan,
Iraq, and other interventions in
the Middle East were justified
as defenses against Islamic
extremism.
All this shows how the legal fact of intervening in a sovereign state or its internal conflicts is always justified by a political vision, which one may or may not share depending on one’s beliefs. The logical consequence is that political facts cannot be judged according to legal principles (such as the principle of non-aggression). In other words, politics operates based on political—not legal—considerations: these are two entirely different realms. The political level is tied to interpretations that derive from ideological principles that vary across time and space and are not universally accepted (such as the principle of nationality, the fight against communism or capitalism, or the threat of religious fanaticism), whereas the legal level relies on principles that are universal and objective.
Returning to the example of Ukraine, it is certainly true from a legal standpoint that Russia invaded Ukraine. But this can be politically interpreted as an action to liberate Russian-speaking compatriots already in revolt and/or to counter NATO’s presence in Ukraine, perceived as a threat to Russia’s survival. Judging these motivations is not a legal matter, but a political one, shaped by differing and conflicting ideologies.
A similar argument applies to
international tribunals, about
which I remain very skeptical.
Take, for instance, the striking
case of Al-Masri, extradited to
Libya by Italian authorities.
It’s one thing if someone is a
bank robber or a wife-killer: no
problem there.
But Al-Masri is accused of
running a horrific prison where
atrocities occurred—which is
likely true. However, consider
that virtually all prisons in
the Middle East, Africa, and
much of the Global South are
like that: why not arrest all
their wardens then? Think of the
sexual violence in Iranian
prisons, what happened to Regeni
in Egypt, or the massacres in
Syria.
And why arrest only Al-Masri and
not the rulers in Tripoli?
We also don’t know if his
successor would be better or
worse.
It’s true these trials damage
the accused’s reputation—but not
in their own countries or
cultures. In fact, such trials
may even enhance their prestige
as heroes resisting the “evil
Western colonialists.”
Indeed, Al-Masri was welcomed
back as a hero. But a hero of
what? Perhaps for scaring the
West?
But beyond the obvious practical difficulties, can we really believe that arresting Putin, Netanyahu, or Al-Masri would change the war in Ukraine, the tragedies in the Middle East, or the fate of migrants? They would simply be replaced by others doing much the same—just as has happened with Hamas leaders.
Israelis have methodically
assassinated all Hamas leaders,
starting with their first, a
blind imam, yet Hamas has not
changed. Even had Rabin not been
killed, the two-state solution
likely would not have happened
due to the rise of religious
fanaticism—both Islamic and
Jewish.
Historical problems cannot be
solved by eliminating those who
lead them.
It is also essential to remember
that the law does not consider
consequences: it simply applies
the rules. Politics, by
contrast, is driven precisely by
consideration of consequences.
What consequences would
Al-Masri’s arrest have had in
our example?
Would peace be more easily
achieved by arresting Putin or
Netanyahu? Certainly not.
Moreover, why do we in the West
claim the right to impose our
principles on countries that do
not accept them?
Can we seriously believe that
some appointed judges are
capable of truly judging
historical events?
In conclusion, I would say that the impossibility of having an international judicial system modeled after the national one is not due to a lack of political will, but to objective reasons.
First and foremost, there is no authority above sovereign states able to enforce such a system: even international bodies (chief among them the UN) are made up of sovereign states, and decisions are taken by majority vote according to political alignments, rather than based on clear legal codes (which are hard to apply even for judges).
Most importantly, principles—and even more so, the interpretation of facts—can vary greatly due to deep cultural differences. Take the Palestinian issue: for Jewish fundamentalists, Palestine was given to the Jews by God; for Islamic fundamentalists, it was given to Muslims. The rest of the world sides with one or the other based on various motivations: anti-colonialism, defense of democracy, or other, sometimes strange, reasons. Everything depends on one’s cultural background.
Can we really believe that such
a complex issue can be resolved
through legal technicalities?
Moreover, considering that the
great civilizations of history
were born through the expansion
of a political entity that
conquered others, can we truly
be certain that aggression
against another state is always
a bad thing?